Contributors

Persons

Places

Terms

Anti-White Buzzwords And Codewords

Article Types

Thursday, 25 May 2017

Civic Nationalism Is Globalism

by Pierre Langelier, contributing to Ocean Drive


Diverse London
London, the capital city of civic nationalist Britain




There are so many inherent contradictions in the concept of civic nationalism that it's hard to know where to even begin. It is described by political philosophers as a "non-xenophobic form of nationalism based on shared values such as freedom, equality, tolerance and individual rights." The fact that very few citizens of modern liberal democracies could even define it is hardly proof of its irrelevance in terms of political discourse; civic nationalism, or citizenship by social contract as opposed to a shared ethnicity or heritage, was the very ideological basis of post-revolutionary France and America and came to be viewed as the most civilized form of Statehood in the post-racial era after WWII.

The fact that Canadian civic nationalists are actually liberals in the classical sense is exemplified by their crusades against Sharia law, and in favour of absolute free speech. They view the encroachment of islam into the public sphere as a violation of secularism, and the recent trends towards the criminalization of blasphemy as an assault on freedom of expression; both of these principles being at the core of the liberal democratic philosophy.

Those who view personal freedom as paramount reject the idea that there is such a thing as a "common good" — they would argue that there are as many conceptions of the good as there are individuals, and that said individuals are free to articulate their lives according to this personal definition of good as long as it doesn't inconvenience their neighbour. According to Canadian professor and philosopher George Grant (1918-1988):
To modern political theory, man's essence is his freedom. Nothing must stand in the way of our absolute freedom to create the world as we want it. There must be no conceptions of good that put limitations on human action.1
This moral relativism is built into civic nationalism's emphasis on a personal definition of the good, and this is why most of its proponents would also tend towards the non-assimilation model of multiculturalism; according to their logic, each racial group is free to pursue their own particular version of the good life as long as they subscribe to the superficial political culture, which is itself far from fixed. They would certainly agree with Frankfurt School philosopher Jürgen Habermas (born 1929), who argued that immigrants' only responsibility is to "assent to the principles of the constitution within the scope of interpretation determined at a particular time."2

Pierre Trudeau's deconstruction of Canadian identity in favor of feel-good pluralism — which few civic nationalists would object to — seemed to foreshadow Habermas's later statement that "in many countries the majority culture is fused with the general political culture...this fusion must be dissolved...the level of the shared political culture must be uncoupled from the level of subcultures and their prepolitical identities."3

The Canadian civic nationalist demand for mere surface-level assimilation by newcomers explains why their only real issue with mass immigration is the threat of islamification. They correctly identify the unlikelihood of "radical" muslim communities abiding by the minimal standards imposed on them in a liberal democracy, whereas they view other ethnic communities, no matter how large, as having no problem in doing so.

By reducing citizenship to compliance with a few legalistic principles, themselves subject to change as morals evolve, civic nationalism inevitably leads to the dissolution of national differences. Its advocates would agree with Francis Fukuyama's oft-quoted statement that liberal democracies represent "the end of History," the final stage in the evolution of Western political systems. Consequently, if civic nationalism represents, in political terms, the "one best means" then, to paraphrase George Grant, how much difference can there be between societies whose faith in "the one best means"4 transcends even cultural and linguistic differences?

This is besides the fact that the tacit acceptance of multicultural doctrine tends towards the elimination of national differences for other, more obvious reasons; nothing is more similar to an egalitarian multiracial nation than another egalitarian multiracial nation. If different societies based on individual rights and freedoms inevitably become indistinguishable from one another, then what is the need for nationalism? Patriotic gestures become another form of virtue-signaling.

Canadian civic nationalists' reluctance to identify themselves, if they are of European descent, as part of a racial group in danger of becoming demographically irrelevant in the very near future, means that their criticisms of globalism are mostly symbolic. The separation of Canadian-ness from any racial connotations, and calls for assimilation being limited to adherence to so-called "Canadian values" (including the supreme value of multiculturalism) leaves all patriotic discourse interchangeable and subject to further deconstruction by the left.

Conservative Party leadership front-runner Maxime Bernier's immigration platform, seen by many as a sane alternative to our current Prime Minister's policies, is nonetheless an example of civic nationalism's inability — or unwillingness — to identify the threat posed by immigration. On his official website, he states that newcomers should be expected to "adopt widely shared Canadian values such as equality of men and women, tolerance for diversity and respect for Canadian law".5 If tomorrow the entire population of Canada was mongrelized into a beige mass of indeterminate ethnicity, while still meeting these lukewarm pre-conditions, something will have been irretrievably lost. What exactly that "something" is, civic nationalists dare not say.

Top 20 de la Diversité

The "Quebec Charter of Values" proposed by the Parti Quebecois under PM Pauline Marois is another example of this. This last stand of Quebec identity, with its neutered vocabulary of shared language, secularism and the equality of men and women suggests that such sterile calls for superficial assimilation typical of civic nationalist discourse are unable to provide sufficient defense against globalism and the dissolution of national differences. The perceived double-standard of maintaining Catholic symbols at the National assembly, unarguably a key component of traditional French Canadian identity, while banning overt religious symbolism such as the hijab in the civil service, reveals the dissonance inherent in civic nationalism.

All efforts to safeguard national uniqueness based solely on legal principles are ultimately futile. The preservation of a shared religious heritage, enforced secularism and religious freedom are mutually exclusive. In refusing to challenge the underlying assumptions about diversity, pluralism, and the Human Rights theology, Canadian civic nationalists cannot claim to represent an effective bulwark against the excesses of cultural Marxism in this country.

The belief in individual freedom over all other considerations leaves them ideologically ill-equipped to reign in the ever-increasing moral decay illustrated by transgender mania for instance; at best their protests are limited to legalistic arguments against the government awarding them special privileges and banning criticism of their "alternative lifestyle". Fundamentally civic nationalism is based on the very notion that all lifestyles are alternatives, and that State-imposed definitions of normalcy are equivalent to authoritarianism.

I recently had the privilege of asking Dr. Kevin B. MacDonald about whether civic nationalism could truly provide a viable solution to the demographic collapse of the White population in Western nations. His answer summed it up nicely:
Civic nationalism is weak tea and not a solution for our problems. (...) I can't see how to restrict immigration within this intellectual framework in a way that would preserve a White majority. And within such a "nation" there is no real intellectual foundation for White identity. (…) Ultimately we have to identify with our people in a racial sense or in the long run it will indeed be genocide.6




[1] George Grant, Lament for a Nation: the Defeat of Canadian Nationalism, McGill-Queen's University Press, 1965, p. 55
[2] Jürgen Habermas, "Struggles for Recognition in the Democratic State," in Inclusion of the Other, MIT Press, 1998, p. 228
[3] Jürgen Habermas, "The European Nation-State: On the Past and Future of Sovereignty and Citizenship," in Inclusion of the Other, MIT Press, 1998, p. 118
[4] Grant's actual quote was "How much difference can there be between societies whose faith in "the one best means" transcends even communist and capitalist differences?" Although he was referring to the homogenizing power of technology, he mentions elsewhere in Lament for a Nation how liberal cosmopolitanism tends towards homogenization.
[5] maximebernier.com: Immigration must not be used as a tool to forcibly change the cultural character and social fabric of Canada
[6] Voat.co: I am Dr. Kevin MacDonald, author of The Culture of Critique and editor of The Occidental Observer. Ask me anything.

No comments:

Post a Comment

The opinions of our commenters do not necessarily represent the opinions of CEC or its contributors. Please follow the netiquette.

Our Facebook Our Twitter Our Gab Our Google+ Our Youtube Our RSS feed